Abstracts

Alan Turing and the Other Theory of Computation

Lenore Blum (Carnegie Mellon University)

CANCELED

Most logicians and theoretical computer scientists are familiar with Alan Turing’s 1936 seminal paper setting the stage for the foundational (discrete) theory of computation. Most however remain unaware of Turing’s 1948 seminal paper introducing the notion of condition, sets the stage for a natural theory of complexity for the “other theory of computation” emanating from the classical tradition of numerical analysis, equation solving and the continuous mathematics of calculus.
This talk will recognize Alan Turing’s work in the foundations of numerical computation (in particular, his 1948 paper “Rounding-Off Errors in Matrix Processes”), its influence in complexity theory today, and how it provides a unifying concept for the two major traditions of the Theory of Computation.

Stable, fractal-based processing of complex languages

Whit Tabor (UConn)

Apr 15, 2pm, LH 302

Consider an iterated map f on a connected space X. A proper subset, A, of X, is said to be asymptotically stable if, when the system is perturbed slightly away from A, it converges back on to A, under continued iteration of f. When one is working in the realm of logic, or classical computation more broadly, stability is not an issue and does not really make sense. There is no possibility of being slightly off—formulas are either well-formed and have precise meaning, or they are ill-formed and they have no meaning at all. Interestingly, in recent decades, a number of people have discovered ways of doing complex computation on connected spaces. This raises the question of whether there could be “stable computation” in such systems. In this talk, I define asymptotic stability for a particular type of connected space computer and show that at least one interesting class of languages (the mirror recursion languages) has a realization which exhibits asymptotic stability of certain fractal sets. One interesting outcome is an answer to the question: Why is there grammaticality?

Alternative logics and abductive methodology

Timothy Williamson (University of Oxford)

23 Mar, 4:30pm, Laurel 201.

The choice between alternative logics can be understood as a special case of theory choice in science, governed by broadly abductive criteria, without appeal to a special relation of logical consequence. This view will be applied to semantic and sorites paradoxes as putative motivations for departures from classical logic.

Objective possibilities

Timothy Williamson (University of Oxford)

22 Mar, 4:30pm, Oak 105.

The categories of metaphysical possibility and metaphysical possibility have been criticized as unscientific and unsuitable for serious theorizing. I will develop an alternative view on which they are limiting cases of a family of objective modalities many members of which are studied in natural science, and discuss the modal aspect of applied mathematics. Some consequences for the logic of metaphysical modality will be discussed.

What if the impossible happened?

Timothy Williamson (University of Oxford)

24 Mar, 4pm, Class of 1947 Room.

If 5+7 had turned out to be 13, everyone would have danced in the streets with joy.” That conditional is true according to standard theories of conditionals, simply because it is impossible for 5 + 7 to turn out to be 13. Many philosophers regard such consequences as obviously wrong. I will explain why significant issues are at stake in this dispute, how our judgments about such matters may be misled by fallible heuristics, and why the standard view may be right after all.

The development of the distinction between formal and material consequence in medieval logic

Jacob Archambault (Fordham University)

19 Feb, 2pm, LH 302.

The idea of a conclusion following formally from a set of premises is central to our conception of logic today: logical consequence is often taken for the subject matter of logic, and ‘formal consequence’ and ‘logical consequence’ are routinely taken as synonyms. It would come as a surprise, then, to know that consequences generally and formal consequence in particular did not always hold this place of prominence: the first treatises specifically devoted to the study of consequences did not appear until the beginning of the fourteenth century – over 1600 years after the death of Aristotle; and the notion of formal consequence didn’t begin to take a shape resembling its modern successor until nearly a half century after these treatises appeared.
Prior to the later nineteenth century, the main developments of the concept of formal consequence as we know it occur in the following stages:

  1. The application of the form/matter distinction to logic;
  2. The earliest implicit appeals to a distinction between formal and material consequence;
  3. The appearance of the earliest treatises on consequences;
  4. The appearance of the first systematic attempts to parse a distinction between formal and material consequence;
  5. The identification of formal consequences with those holding for all permutations of categorematic terms;
  6. The identification of formal consequence with logical consequence;
  7. The identification of logical consequence as the subject matter of logic.

All but the first and last of these developments occur in a period of intense logical activity stretching from about 1285 to 1341, just over half a century. This talk provides an overview of the developments of this period. I begin with an outline of the topical tradition on which earlier treatises on consequences depended. Next, I detail the account of John Buridan, whose distinction between formal and material consequences is more familiar than others, both because it has been better researched and because of its basic similarity to modern model-theoretic accounts. From here, I move backward to the previous developments Buridan’s account relies on and engages with, particularly those of William of Ockham and Walter Burley.

On Unidirectionality in Precisification

Peter Klecha (University of Connecticut)

4 Dec, 2pm, LH 302.

This talk provides a formal pragmatic analysis of (im)precision which accounts for its essential properties, but also for Lewis’s (1979) observation of asymmetry in how standards of precision may shift in a given discourse: Only up, not down. I propose that shifts of the kind observed and discussed by Lewis are in fact cases of underlying disagreement about the standard of precision, which is only revealed when one interlocutor uses an expression which signals their adherence to a higher standard than the one adhered to be the other interlocutor(s). I show that a modest formal pragmatic analysis along the lines of game-theoretic approaches by Franke (2009), Jaeger (2012) and others can easily capture the natural asymmetry in standard-signaling that gives rise to Lewis’s observation, so long as such an account is enriched with a notion of relevance. If there’s time, I’ll also discuss how this approach can be helpful for understanding a longstanding puzzle in the semantics of counterfactuals, namely the issue of Sobel Sequences and their reversals.

Size and Function

Bruno Whittle (Yale University)

6 Nov, 2pm, LH 302.

The talk will be about a question that is generally taken to be settled: are there different sizes of infinity? That is, are there infinite sets of different sizes? This is one of the most natural questions that one can ask about the infinite. But it is of course generally taken to be settled by results, such as Cantor’s theorem, to the effect that there are infinite sets without bijections between them. These results (which I of course do not dispute) answer the question given an almost universally accepted principle relating size to the existence of functions. The principle is: for any sets A and B, if A is the same size as B, then there is a bijection from A to B. The aim of the talk, however, is to argue that the question is in fact wide open: to argue that we are not in a position to know the answer, because we are not in a position to know this principle. I will do this by looking at what seem to be the strongest reasons for thinking that we are in a position to know the principle, and arguing against them.

A New (Linguistic) Approach to Logical Pluralism

Teresa Kouri (Ohio State University)

13 Nov, 2pm, LH 302.

There are several options for logical pluralism on the table. Rudolf Carnap puts forward a position in which the logical connectives never mean the same thing in distinct logics, and JC Beall & Greg Restall put forward a position in which they always do. However, neither of them are capable of accounting for all of our intuitions. In particular, neither Carnap nor Beall & Restall can make sense of the fact that it seems there are some contexts in which distinct logics seem to have the same logical terminology, and some context in which distinct logics have distinct logical terminology. In this paper, I will present a view (in line with that of Stewart Shapiro’s) which can account for both of these intuitions.